Appiah Essay Summary Statements

Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers
by Kwame Anthony Appiah
196pp, Allen Lane, £16.99

Prehistoric hunter-gatherers encountered fewer people in a lifetime than we would on a single day walking down New York's Fifth Avenue. Though their world of isolated clans shaped our natures, we live in a world where our most trivial deeds can affect unknown millions on the other side of the globe. Kwame Anthony Appiah, an Anglo-Ghanaian philosophy professor based at Princeton, proposes two principles to enable us to cope with this situation. We are, he asserts, responsible for every other human being. This may seem vapid - the kind of pious over-statement beloved of international organisations. But Appiah takes it seriously, and tries to impose realistic limits on an apparently open-ended duty.

By refusing to equate not saving a person with killing him, except where propinquity places us in a special relationship to his death, Appiah argues that we are not obliged to give all our material wealth to aid the third world. He thinks it may seem shocking that he defends going to the opera when children are dying. According to him, we can do most good not by depriving ourselves of pleasures, but by pondering on the root causes of these ills, and influencing larger policy decisions.

Appiah's second principle advocates "universal concern and respect for legitimate difference". This raises the question of how we are to respect cultural diversity and yet not condone cruel and barbarous social practices, such as the stoning of an adulteress. Can Appiah prevent his cosmopolitanism from degenerating into an "anything goes" morality? Relativism, he tells us, arises out of a scientific view that sharply distinguishes facts from values. Facts, on this view, are out there in the world, and since there is only one world, our beliefs are true when they correspond with the facts. Values are merely matters of taste and so immune from rational criticism: if stoning an adulteress is regarded as good by certain societies, it is good for them.

Appiah resists this conclusion by arguing that values are more tethered to reason than is here allowed. We do not learn that kindness is good, or cruelty evil, by experience as we learn that chocolate is nice. Goodness is integral to kindness, and evil to cruelty, so that in grasping these concepts we recognise that we all have good reason to be kind, and to abhor cruelty. It is because we value kindness that we want people to be kind, not the other way around.

But don't values still fall short of the standard of rationality by which we measure beliefs? Appiah replies that even a person's beliefs are only rational relative to the beliefs he already possesses. It is no more irrational for a member of the Asante clan to believe that his aunt's illness is caused by her daughter-in-law's witchcraft than for a person in Manhattan to believe that a virus is responsible. The westerner does not see viruses invading cells any more than the Asante sees witches producing their malign effects. When scientists looked at photographs of cloud chambers they saw fuzzy lines which it was rational to interpret as the paths of electrons only because of prior theoretical beliefs. Appiah concludes that "you can't get into the game of belief by starting from nothing". However, he rejects the view that we cannot adjudicate between beliefs in witchcraft and viruses. The former, he declares, are false, the latter true; the theories and ideas of science are "far superior" to those of pre-scientific societies. By Appiah's own reckoning, this judgment is rational only relative to the beliefs he already possesses. Surely, if these beliefs are scientific, he is begging the question in favour of science, and his retreat from relativism is blocked.

Drawing vividly upon his experiences of growing up in Ghana, Appiah argues that moral and religious disagreement between cultures is overstated. It will seem less strange that in Akan society a woman's eldest brother assumes the role of father to her children when we realise that his conduct is assessed by the same criteria as a father's in our society. Taboos, such as that against eating red pepper on Wednesdays, cannot be brought under familiar moral principles, but we know what it is like to feel polluted.

Aspects of western culture - radios, Coca-cola, a passion for football - have spread to remote Ghanaian villages, and so aid mutual understanding. Where disagreements are real, it is rarely a problem unique to cosmopolitanism since they also occur - consider the controversy over homosexuality - within societies. Conflicts sometimes arise because we share the same value: Palestinians and Israelis clash over Jerusalem because they prize it equally. Appiah will perhaps be accused of underestimating the gulf of incomprehension that exists between fundamentalists of different religious persuasions, but his sensible optimism is a refreshing antidote to today's scare-mongering pessimism.

· Sophie Botros is the author of Hume, Reason and Morality: A Legacy of Contradiction (Routledge).

17.1 Wittgenstein

In both his so-called “early” and “late” periods, Wittgenstein focuses on an analysis of language. If we can come to a proper understanding of language, he claims, then all the traditional philosophical problems can be solved.

A proper understanding involves correctly grasping the logical structure of language. This understanding means we will know what can be said plainly and clearly, and what cannot. Unfortunately, philosophers don’t know this distinction, and so spend time trying to say what cannot be said, written, or thought. Meaningful propositions are restricted to natural science; nonsensical propositions occur in metaphysics, religion, and ethics.

Wittgenstein’s picture theory of meaning provides a framework within which to understand his idea of a meaningful proposition: a proposition is a picture, a single logical structure that corresponds exactly to a particular structure in the world. This theory expresses the view that the logical structures of language mirror the structures of the world.

Wittgenstein’s later period of philosophical activity is concerned not with the essence of language, but its many functions and forms. He focuses his thought on a theory of language as a game, a pattern of social activity in which words play a crucial role and derive their meaning from how they are used in the activity.

17.2 Derrida and Cixous

Jacques Derrida is most famous for the deconstruction method of dissecting language. Deconstruction is a way of unpacking a text to reveal hidden assumptions and contradictions that subvert the ostensible meaning. One of those assumptions Derrida terms logocentrism, the preoccupation with truth, logic, and rationality that characterizes the Western intellectual tradition. This means, among other things, that we take language to be static, fixed, when in fact it is fluid and changeable, when meanings are slippery.

Derrida’s colleague Hélène Cixous has written on a remarkably broad array of topics, but has written most extensively on the philosophical and psychological implications of the act of writing.

17.3 Rawls

Perhaps the most important political philosopher of the 20th century, John Rawls advanced a sort of social contract theory. As we recall from Chapter 10, a social contract theory asserts that justice is secure, and the state is made legitimate, through an agreement among citizens of the state or between the citizens and rulers of the state.

Rawls argues that since people’s character and behavior are accidents of nature, no one really deserves any particular allotment of benefits or burdens. A staunch egalitarianism demands that the supposedly deserving, undeserving, needy, and self-sufficient receive the same slice of society’s pie.

An ingenious thought experiment rooted in the useful fiction of social contracts allows Rawls to explore the requirements of distributive justice. The sort of social contract that would best ensure a fair distribution of rights, duties, and advantages of social cooperation can be established if we imagine we live in an “original position” in the state of nature. We are rationally self-interested individuals who meet behind a “veil of ignorance,” where the particularities of our lives are hidden to us. All we have is our rational self-interest. From the standpoint, we will choose nondiscriminatory and unbiased principles.

17.4 Appiah

A major focus of Kwame Anthony Appiah’s work is the social and ethical questions that arise from the collision of cultures in a shrinking world. Appiah proposes cosmopolitanism as a solution. Cosmopolitanism is the idea that we have moral duties to all persons, even those outside our family and community. These duties Appiah believes are rooted in objective, universal values.

17.5 Nussbaum

Nussbaum is a philosopher who believes philosophy should be applicable to daily life. Toward this end, she has taken on some of the most serious societal concerns of our times—among them, sex and social justice, feminism, religious intolerance, gay rights, race and international development, moral relativism, democracy, and education. Her overriding view is the importance of equal moral respect for all individuals.

17.6 Martin Luther King, Jr.

Best known for his central, galvanizing role in the American civil rights movement and for his compelling calls for justice and equality, Martin Luther King, Jr. advocated a Gandhian type of nonviolent protest. It is the middle road between the paths of militant violence and nonviolent inaction.



0 comments

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *